Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-42gr6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T20:29:32.425Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Authoritarian Constitutionalism

Some Conceptual Issues

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Mark Tushnet
Affiliation:
Northwestern University
Tom Ginsburg
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Alberto Simpser
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Get access

Summary

Legal scholars and political theorists interested in constitutionalism as a normative concept tend to dichotomize the subject. There is liberal constitutionalism of the sort familiar in the modern West, with core commitments to human rights and self-governance implemented by means of varying institutional devices, and there is authoritarianism, rejecting human rights entirely and governed by unconstrained power holders. Charles McIlwain's often-quoted words exemplify the dichotomization: “[C]onstitutionalism has one essential quality; it is a legal limitation on government; it is the antithesis of arbitrary rule; its opposite is despotic government, the government of will instead of law,” and “[a]ll constitutional government is by definition limited government” (1947: 20–1).

This chapter explores the possibility, perhaps implicit in a restrained understanding of McIlwain's formulation, of forms of constitutionalism other than liberal constitutionalism. After describing two possibilities – absolutist constitutionalism and “mere” rule-of-law constitutionalism – the chapter examines in more detail what I call authoritarian constitutionalism. That discussion is connected to recent literature in political science on hybrid regimes that have been labeled variously electoral authoritarianism (Schedler 2006) and competitive authoritarianism (Levitsky and Way 2010). The literature in political science is more concerned with the conditions for the emergence and stability of hybrid regimes than with normative issues, but some parts of the literature shed light on normative issues, as does the related literature on the functions of constitutions and courts in truly authoritarian regimes. Drawing on these literatures, this chapter outlines some characteristics of authoritarian constitutionalism understood normatively.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Advisory Council on the Impact of New Media on Society, The. 2008. Engaging New Media: Challenging Old Assumptions (report).
Baogang, He and Warren, Mark E.. 2011. “Authoritarian Deliberation: The Deliberative Turn in Chinese Political Development.” Perspectives on Politics 9: 269.Google Scholar
Case, William. “Manipulative Skills: How Do Rulers Control the Electoral Arena?” in Schedler, Andreas, ed., Electoral Authoritarianism: The Dynamics of Unfree Competition. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 2006.Google Scholar
Chng Suan Tze v. Minister of Home Affairs. 1989. MLJ 1: 69 (Singapore Court of Appeal).
Christiano, Thomas. 2011. “An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 39: 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Constitution of Singapore.
Fuller, Lon. 1964. The Morality of Law. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ginsburg, Tom and Moustafa, Tamir (eds.). 2008. Rule by Law: The Politics of Courts in Authoritarian Regimes. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Issacharoff, Samuel and Pildes, Richard. 1998. “Politics as Markets: Partisan Lockups of the Democratic Process.” Stanford Law Review 50: 643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kumar, Sree and Siddique, Sharon. 2010. The Singapore Success Story: Public–Private Alliance for Investment Attraction, Innovation and Export Development 15. New York: United Nations.Google Scholar
Levitsky, Steven and Way, Lucan A.. 2002. “The Rise of Competitive Authoritarianism.” Journal of Democracy 13: 51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levitsky, Steven and Way, Lucan A.. 2010. Competitive Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes After the Cold War. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magaloni, Beatriz. 2006. Voting for Autocracy: Hegemonic Party Survival and Its Demise in Mexico. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayhew, David. 1974. Congress: The Electoral Connection. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
McIlwain, Charles. 1947. Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Moustafa, Tamir. 2007. The Struggle for Constitutional Power: Law, Politics, and Development in Egypt. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mydans, Seth. 2008. “J. B. Jeyaretnam, Persistent Opposition Figure in Singapore, Is Dead at 82.” The New York Times (5 October 2008), 43.
Obituary. “Joshua B. Jeyaretnam: Singapore Opposition Leader.” The Times Online (1 October 2008). Available at (visited 28 September 2011).
Okoth-Okendo, H. W. O. 1993. “Constitutions without Constitutionalism: An African Political paradox,” in Douglas Greenberg, Katz, S. N., Oliviero, B., and Wheatley, S. C., eds., Constitutionalism and Democracy: Transitions in the Contemporary World. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 65–80.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schedler, Andreas (ed.). 2006. Electoral Authoritarianism: The Dynamics of Unfree Competition. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Schedler, Andreas. 2009. “Electoral Authoritarianism,” in Landman, Todd and Robinson, Neil, eds., The Sage Handbook of Comparative Politics. Los Angeles: Sage, pp. 381–94.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Gordon. 2008. “Singapore: The Exception that Proves Rules Matter,” in Ginsburg, Tom and Moustafa, Tamir, eds., Rule by Law: The Politics of Courts in Authoritarian Regimes. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp.73–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tushnet, Mark. 2012. “Constitutions,” in Rosenfeld, Michel and Sajo, Andras, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Constitutional Law. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 217–32.Google Scholar
Wikipedia. Group Representation Constituency. Available at .
Rawls, John, The Law of Peoples (1999)
Moustafa, Tamir, The Struggle for Constitutional Power: Law, Politics, and Development in Egypt (2007)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×