This article expands our understanding of the historical development of just war thought by offering the first detailed analysis of the ethics of war in ancient Egypt. It revises the standard history of the just war tradition by demonstrating that just war thought developed beyond the boundaries of Europe and existed many centuries earlier than the advent of Christianity or even the emergence of Greco-Roman doctrine. It also argues that the creation of a prepotent ius ad bellum doctrine in ancient Egypt—based on universal and absolutist claims to justice—hindered the development of ius in bello norms in Egyptian warfare. I contend that this development prefigures similar developments in certain later Western and Near Eastern doctrines of just war and holy war.

Johnson (1981, 1984, 1999, 2011) has long stressed the importance of a historical understanding of the just war tradition. An increasing body of work draws our attention to the pre-Christian origins of just war thought.1 Nonetheless, scholars and politicians continue to overdraw the association between Christian political theology and the advent of just war thought. This reinforces the common misconception that just war is an exclusively Christian doctrine, and, in consequence, “curtails its appeal in parts of the world that historically have no affinity with Christianity” (O’Driscoll 2015, 1–2).

This article strengthens and expands the scope of the historical just war argument by demonstrating that complex considerations of the relationship between war and justice existed more than two thousand years prior to the advent of Christianity. In providing the first major exposition of the ancient Egyptian ethics of war, I offer further evidence that just war thought developed beyond the traditional boundaries of Europe. Moreover, I identify some compelling (albeit speculative) reasons to think that elements of Egyptian thought about war might have influenced the later Western tradition.2

Despite the chronological and cultural distance between them, rethinking modern assumptions in the light of ancient doctrines and practices can be illuminating. On the one hand, I highlight how absolutist or universalizing concepts of justice can generate potent ius ad bellum doctrines. On the other hand, I caution that prepotent ius ad bellum doctrines can make the resort to war more likely and, by hindering the development or application of ius in bello norms, more destructive. Indeed, I suggest that assumptions of universal justice continue to have a negative impact upon modern conflicts.

This article concentrates on Egyptian ideology and warfare during the three major periods of centralized monarchy: the Old Kingdom (2686–2181 BCE), Middle Kingdom (2055–1650 BCE), and New Kingdom (1552–1069 BCE).3 During this time the Egyptians suffered and repulsed invasions while also pursuing imperialist policies of their own in Nubia (modern southern Egypt and northern Sudan), Libya, and Syria-Palestine.4 The Egyptian state engaged in warfare and diplomacy with a variety of states and peoples over the course of its long history. There existed no “international organizations, law codes or jurists” between the third and first millennia BCE, but we can detect “a recognizable international legal community” in the area from the Nile to the Tigris-Euphrates (Ziskind 1967, 202–3).5 Within this international legal community, Egypt developed its own distinctive ethics of war, yet scholars pay little attention to the emergence of Egyptian just war thought.6

The ethics of war in ancient Egypt was founded upon three tenets of Egyptian culture that displayed remarkable longevity and consistency: 1) the cosmological role of Egypt, 2) the divine office of the pharaoh, and 3) the superiority of the land of Egypt and its inhabitants over all other lands and peoples. These ideological foundations led the Egyptian political elite to develop an ethics of war that possessed elements analogous to later Western concepts of proper authority and just cause: so-called ius ad bellum criteria. The relationship between war and justice in Egyptian culture was so intimate that we can identify an ancient Egyptian just war doctrine. Egyptian pharaohs claimed exclusive possession of legitimate authority and just cause in warfare. In contrast, while the conduct of Egyptian warfare followed a small number of norms, the development of in bello restraints are invisible to the historian.7 Egyptian warfare was brutal, yet this lack of restraint was partly rooted in the conviction that the possession and defense of justice was integral to the wars in which Egypt engaged. As a consequence, the state had a free hand in prosecuting wars in whatever manner it saw fit.

The first part of this article analyzes Egyptian political theology and its creation of ius ad bellum concepts regarding legitimate authority and just cause. The second part reflects on Egyptian conduct in bello through examining the mechanisms of Egyptian warfare, including the conduct of war, the conceptualization and treatment of enemy persons and property, and the role of diplomacy. In the conclusion, I suggest that the ancient Egyptian concept of just war can be grouped with certain other just war doctrines that have emerged over time and across cultures, specifically those sharing claims to universal or absolute justice.

Ius ad bellum

Authority

Polities throughout the ancient Near East held that divine authority was mediated through the figure of the king. Egypt was somewhat anomalous in that, from the Early Dynastic period (c. 3100–2686 BCE), Egyptian kings assumed an even greater authority. They became not only agents of the gods but figures who fulfilled a divine office and attained a quasi-divine status.8 The divine aspects of the pharaoh’s office remained closely linked to his martial role. Senusret I (1965–1920 BCE) claimed that: “I was nursed to be a conqueror…his [Atum] son and his protector, he gave me to conquer what he conquered.”9

From the Middle Kingdom onward, Egyptian pharaohs increasingly associated themselves with the high god Amun-Re. As the “son” of Amun-Re, the pharaoh possessed an incontestable legitimacy to wage war, not only on behalf of Amun-Re—whose support was tacit—but also on his own authority as a quasi-divine being. This built on earlier royal ideology. During the Old Kingdom, the authority of the terrestrial “son of Horus” to act with impunity against Egypt’s neighbors was so axiomatic that “no king felt the need to justify such action” (Redford 1995, 165). Menu (2003, 53) interprets the Old Kingdom Pyramid Texts as presenting war as self-legitimizing—“a way for the king to fulfill his obligations with regard to his subjects, and a validation of his functions, regarding his status as a god-king.”10

To reaffirm his relationship with the gods and to emphasize the divine sanction of military ventures, pharaohs visited cult centers—especially Karnak—prior to embarking on campaigns. Here the pharaoh would “receive” commands from the god(s).11 For example, Pharaoh Kamose (1555–1550 BCE) stated: “I went north because I was strong (enough) to attack the Asiatics through the command of Amon, the just of counsels.”12 Pharaoh Merneptah (1213–1203 BCE) stressed the divine protection enjoyed by Egypt: “None who attacks her people will succeed. The eye of every god is after her despoiler. It will make an end of all its foes.”13 The authority and interests of gods and pharaoh were essentially indivisible and, by the nature of their divine origin, in accord with justice. Thutmose III (1456–1427 BCE) erected a stela at the temple of Amun (Karnak) that provides an unequivocal statement of the pharaoh’s divine mandate to wage war on his enemies:

I [Amun] gave you valor and victory over all lands…

The princes of all lands are gathered in your grasp…

I fettered Nubia’s Bowmen by ten thousand thousands,

The northerners a hundred thousand captives.

I made your enemies succumb beneath your soles,

So that you crushed the rebels and the traitors.

For I bestowed on you the earth, its length and breadth,

Westerners and easterners are under your command.14

According to Thutmose III’s political theology, the authority to wage war was founded upon a divine grant of universal sovereignty over all lands and peoples. Black (2009, 24) observes that this is “the earliest record of nationalist imperialism and divinely mandated universal empire.” Consequently, the Egyptian monarchy interpreted any challenge or threat as an act of rebellion. Egyptian conceptualization of universal authority, which rendered all enemies—internal or external—rebels, served to delegitimize the military actions of enemy peoples while at the same time legitimizing the martial actions of the state. As we shall see, it justified any offensive war as a defensive act to restore the natural political order, as understood by Egypt (Shaw 1991, 7). This concept of divine sovereignty and jurisdiction was repeated throughout Egyptian texts and iconography. It highlights the crucial link in Egyptian culture between authority and legitimate warfare.

The authority of the pharaoh to wage war stemmed not only from his divine office but also from the unique cosmological status of his kingdom. Egypt was regarded as the terrestrial embodiment of the universal politico-theological principle of order and justice: Ma’at. This pivotal attribute made Egypt and Egyptians superior to all other lands and peoples.15Ma’at—personified as a female deity—appears as a principle of right action early in Egyptian history.16 But the creative harmony of Ma’at was perpetually threatened by the destructive forces of chaos (Isfet), which the Egyptians identified terrestrially as foreign peoples beyond their realm as well as criminal and rebellious elements within it. This fundamental duality of justice and order versus injustice and chaos was naturally translated into the dichotomy of peace and war. Ancient Egyptian literature expresses a deep-seated hostility toward “barbaric” foreigners and the threat they posed to civilized society. This hostility is especially vivid in prophetic “lament” poetry, probably originating in the Middle Kingdom but surviving only in New Kingdom copies:

Destroyed indeed are those things of happiness…the land is laid low with pain, by those feeding Syrians who go throughout the land. Enemies have arisen in the East! Asiatics have come down to Egypt; a secure stronghold is lacking…I shall show you the land in catastrophe, what should not happen, happening: arms of war will be taken up, and the land will live by uproar.17

Only the return of a true king could restore Ma’at: “Asiatics will fall to his slaughtering, and Libyans will fall to his flame. Rebels belong to his rage, and malcontents to his awesomeness…And the Walls of the Ruler will be built. There will be no letting Asiatics come down to Egypt…Truth will return to its proper place, with Chaos driven outside.”18

Just Cause

The defense of Ma’at was central to the ancient Egyptian concept of just cause. Within the broader conception of justice, the principles of reciprocity and retribution were of fundamental importance. Retributive justice pervaded all levels of Egyptian society. In royal ideology, criminal law, or private religion, Egyptians subscribed to a basic moral causality, which held that good actions brought positive consequences while evil actions brought negative consequences.19 This was central to ideas of good government, with violence and avarice being commonly recognized as key expressions of injustice.20 This understanding of justice stipulated that it was morally right that enemies of Egypt—cast as violators of order and justice (Ma’at)—should bear the evil consequences of punitive war and defeat. Such enemies were, by definition, evil, and all actions against them were justified as part of a natural system of reciprocity and retribution. Of course, this conception of justice was entirely stacked in favor of the Egyptians. Ma’at resided in Egypt, and the pharaoh was the sole guardian and absolute judge of matters pertaining to Ma’at. Therefore, any assault upon Egypt or Egyptian interests was ipso facto unjust.

Self-defense against barbarians was the quintessential casus belli. Gnirs (1999, 73) observes that “war was conceived of as the inevitable answer to enemy provocation.” In this, Egyptian attitudes bear comparison to later classical Greek ideas about the natural animosity that existed between Greeks and barbarians (non-Hellenes).21

A laudatory hymn to Senusret III (1874–1855 BCE) expresses a clear sense of repelling injury and defending the innocent against external threats: “He came and fought [on] his frontier: He rescued him who had been robbed!”22 Pharaoh Kamose justified his wars against the Hyksos invaders on the basis that “No man can settle down, being despoiled by the imposts of the Asiatics. I will grapple with him, that I may cut open his belly! My wish is to save Egypt and to smite the Asiatics!”23 The protective and punitive functions of the pharaoh were central to his obligations to his people, his land, and his gods. Violence against enemies was a just retributive response to injuries (actual or potential) suffered by Egypt.24 Pharaohs frequently expanded this concept of self-defense to include aggressive wars waged beyond the borders of Egypt.25 In a very concrete sense, the cosmological conception of Egypt as the sole residence of order and justice meant that all Egyptian wars were defensive, as foes were representative of chaos and constantly threatened peace and security.

The imperialistic New Kingdom witnessed a concerted policy of extending the borders of Egypt. The legitimacy of this expansionist policy derived from the royal ideology of divine sanction and universal jurisdiction, enjoyed by pharaohs since at least the Middle Kingdom. The empire reached its territorial apogee under Thutmose III (1456–1427 BCE), stretching from the Euphrates in the northeast, to beyond the Fourth Cataract of the Nile in the south (central Sudan). Thutmose III left extensive written records of his campaigns in the form of stelae and Annals inscribed on temple walls. We are told that the pharaoh departed on campaign “in valor, might, and right, to overthrow that wretched enemy, to extend the borders of Egypt, his father, mighty and victorious Amun, having commanded that he conquer.”26 The universal sovereignty of the Egyptian monarch sanctioned the violent subjugation of “barbarian” lands:

I [Amun-Re] came to let you tread on those of Asia…
I came to let you tread on eastern lands…
I came to let you tread on western lands…
I came to let you tread on lowlanders…
I came to let you tread on islanders…
I let them see your majesty as the avenger…
I came to let you tread on earth’s limits…27

Celebrating martial deeds against injustice was essential in promoting the valor of the pharaoh. Seti I (1294–1279 BCE) boasted that he “exults at undertaking combat…his heart is satisfied at the sight of blood. He cuts off the heads of the perverse of heart.”28 The act of war became an aspect of the pharaoh’s perpetual struggle against the forces of chaos (Spalinger 2005, 78). Owing to the supernatural origins and superhuman strength of the pharaoh, his victory is depicted in the sources as inevitable. The contest is intrinsically asymmetric, and there is no sense that it is or should be a fair fight.29 From the reign of Amenhotep II (1427–1400 BCE), reaching a climax under Ramses II (1279–1213 BCE), the valor of the pharaoh was exaggerated to such an extent that the deeds of the Egyptian soldiery were frequently ignored or even explicitly denigrated in order to magnify the heroism of the monarch.30

Concepts of Rebellion

Ma’at was thought to be a divine principle that all humans should respect and follow. Identifying enemies (internal and external) as traitors against Ma’at enabled essentially aggressive wars to be couched in terms of punitive violence against rebellion. The punishment for such “rebellion” was equally harsh for native Egyptians and foreigners alike.31 While no ancient Egyptian law codes proper have survived, a reconstruction of criminal law from a range of texts evinces that those who violated Ma’at faced a variety of corporal and capital punishments. These included flogging, mutilation (such as cutting off noses and ears), impalement, and burning. Crimes against the king (treason) or the gods (misappropriation of temple property, tomb robbery) were archetypal capital offenses.32 The Middle Kingdom ruler, Senusret I, justified horrific acts of violence against those implicated in civil war on the basis that they were legitimate punishments for rebellion and for the destruction of religious property within Egypt:

[A]s for them that had transgressed against this house (the temple at Tod). My Majesty made [a great slaughter among them…] both men and women, the valleys being filled with rows (?) (of cadavers), the mountains bearing sheaves (of corpses); the enemy from the “Terraces” were placed on the brazier—it was death by fire because of what they had done against it…the young were sawn up, the children of the enemy were like sacrificial victims.33

In this case there was clearly a judgment of corporate guilt, with women and children suffering the same gruesome fate as the men.

As Egyptian imperial power matured, it exported the punishment of rebellion beyond its traditional frontiers. Rebellion features prominently in the records of military campaigns as a cause for war. Thutmose I (1504–1492 BCE) invaded Nubia “to crush rebellion throughout the lands,” while Thutmose III’s expedition to Megiddo (in Syria-Palestine) was intended “to kill the treacherous ones who were in it and to give things to those who were loyal to him.”34 The campaigns of Amenhotep II were framed in similar terms: “He surrounded everyone rebellious to him and killed them, like those who have never existed, put on (their) side, upside down.”35 Even the Hittite protagonists at Ramses II’s great battle at Kadesh (1274 BCE) were described as rebels.36 This claim had no basis in political reality, only in the justification for punitive warfare contained within Egyptian political theology.

In bello norms

Preparing for War

The opening of hostilities between Egypt and an enemy was probably marked by some sort of declaration of war; the time and site of battle might also have been prearranged.37 While there is little direct evidence for either practice, the negative stereotype of the “miserable Asiatic” was confirmed by their failure to declare war: He does not announce the day of combat, Like a thief who darts about a group.”38 A later example records how the Kushite pharaoh Piye (736–712 BCE, Third Intermediate Period) commanded his generals to make overt declarations of war, even allowing the enemy time to gather his full host:

Do not attack by night…fight when one can see. Challenge him to battle from afar. If he proposes to await the infantry and chariotry of another town, then sit still until his troops come. Fight when he proposes…let them be challenged to battle in advance, saying: “You whose name we do not know…form your battle line, and know that Amun is the god who sent us!”39

The order forbidding night attacks suggests that such operations were somehow dishonorable, and is reminiscent of the condemnation of Asiatics as thieves who do not declare war (above). However, Piye’s decision to allow his enemy time to gather troops was more likely strategic—to force a decisive battle—than “chivalric” (Chevereau 1999). The order forbidding night attacks and to “fight when one can see” might have been motivated simply by operational practicality, or by Piye’s desire that his subjects should be able to witness his victory. The stela inscription is a piece of propaganda intended to magnify the pharaoh’s martial prowess. Moreover, Egyptian preparations for war included practices that were intended to produce an asymmetric advantage. Magical operations attempted to harness occult powers prior to campaigns in order to curse enemies through sympathetic magic and even human sacrifice. The ritual cursing and destruction of symbolic objects and victims was intended to precipitate the destruction of the enemy before any military operations had even begun; clearly this excluded any sense of equity.40

Weapons and Tactics

Once hostilities had begun, there were very few restraints on Egyptian military conduct. In ancient Greece and medieval Europe, for example, some minimal efforts were made to restrict the usage of missile weapons.41 No such restrictions existed within Egyptian martial culture. Archery had been utilized in Near Eastern warfare since circa 12,000–9000 BCE. The discovery of bows and arrows in elite Egyptian tombs, as well as numerous images depicting pharaohs using bows to fell their enemies, confirms the high social status of these weapons.42 There appear to have been few or no accords governing military operations once foes met in the field: espionage, ambush, and deceit were all acceptable.43 A Dynasty XIX manuscript (c. 1300 BCE) tells of how Thutmose III seized the city of Joppa by hiding two hundred soldiers inside baskets that were then smuggled into the city (Pritchard 1969, 23).44

Treatment of the Enemy

The vast majority of evidence surviving from ancient Egypt creates the strong impression that Egyptians regarded foreigners and enemies with contempt. Egyptians considered the “vile Asiatic” to be “the pain of the place where he is.”45 Typical of this attitude is Senusret III’s description of Nubian enemies: “They are not people one respects, They are wretches, craven-hearted.”46 But, Egyptians dismissed such “barbarians” as cowardly and as a constant blight to “civilized” society.

This contempt for alien peoples was reflected in the deeply asymmetric status of Egyptian soldiers in relation to enemy combatants and non-combatants.47 Brutal treatment of the enemy during and after military engagements was normative. The killing of enemy soldiers, the enslavement of defeated combatants and non-combatants, and the destruction of non-combatant property were taken for granted. The Autobiography of Ahmose Son of Abana records jubilantly that during a campaign in Nubia, “a slaughter was made among them; their dependents were carried off as living captives…and that wretched Nubian Bowman head downward at the bow of his majesty’s ship ‘Falcon.’”48 Two generations later, in a war against the Naharin, Thutmose III boasted that “I desolated his towns and his tribes and set fire to them. I captured all their people, carried off as living prisoners…and their goods as well. I took away the very sources of life.49 Clearly these campaign records adopt standard literary conventions, yet they also demonstrate an assumption that the mass slaughter and enslavement of the enemy was a good thing—something to extol and to boast about.50 Recurring Egyptian battle motifs characterized the enemy as physically and morally inferior to Egyptians, especially to the pharaoh (O’Connor 2003, 156–57; David 2011). Amenhotep II even described enemy kingdoms as women whom he had raped.51

Mutilation of the Dead

The preservation and return of enemy corpses—informed and enforced by religious duty—appears to have been a strong norm in late archaic and classical Greek warfare.52 In contrast, some of the earliest artefacts from ancient Egypt provide evidence of the deliberate mutilation of enemy corpses. The Narmer Palette (c. 3100 BCE, Figure 1) shows the triumphant pharaoh inspecting rows of decapitated corpses.53 It was standard practice for the enemy dead to be counted by the number of hands, ears, or phalli collected after battle. In return for presenting these trophies to the military commander, warriors were awarded the “Gold of Valor” or “Gold of Favor.”54 This practice is attested in the Biography of Amenemheb: “I made captives in the king’s presence; I took a hand there, and he gave me the Gold of Favor” (Pritchard 1969, 241). Ahmose son of Abana boasted that he had “been rewarded with gold seven times” in return for presenting hands to the pharaoh.55 An inscription at Karnak from Merneptah’s reign records: “asses…laden with the uncircumcised phalli of the land of Libya, together with the severed hands of [every?] country which was with them.”56 Given the importance that Egyptians attached to the preservation of the flesh for burial (McDermott 2004, 17), the mutilation of enemy corpses—even for mundane purposes such as tallying the dead—must have been understood by Egyptians as a deliberate act of violation. This derogatory act conveyed a message of humiliation, retribution, and warning to existing and potential enemies.
Figure 1.

The Narmer palette (c. 3100 BCE), depicting the execution of prisoners of war (left) and decapitated enemy corpses (top right)65

Prisoners of War

All prisoners of war were the de iure property of the pharaoh. Soldiers were required to present their captives to the central administration, which then decided on redistribution.57 Many prisoners of war were gifted to the temples—especially the Temple of Amun at Karnak—because slaves were understood to constitute part of the gods’ rightful booty in helping bring about victory.

After capture, prisoners enjoyed no immunities or rights. This applied across the social spectrum, with high-ranking prisoners arguably at greater risk than anyone else.58 The status and treatment of Egyptian prisoners of war was hardly unique in the ancient world. It very much mirrors later Greek convention, whereby the “victor had the option of killing the enemy soldiers on the spot, enslaving them, or exchanging them for ransom” (Lanni 2008, 480).

A gruesome piece of political theater performed by Amenhotep II illustrates the mortal danger that captured enemy leaders faced:

His majesty returned in joy of heart to this father Amon, when he had slain with his own mace the seven princes…who had been put upside down at the prow of his majesty’s falcon-boat…Then six men of these enemies were hanged on the face of the wall of Thebes, and the hands as well. Then the other foe was taken upstream to the land of Nubia and hanged to the wall of Napata, to show his majesty’s victories forever and ever in all lands and all countries…59

On a separate occasion, Amenhotep II presided over a mass holocaust of enemy prisoners of both sexes and all ages, demonstrating that the risk of summary execution extended to non-elite prisoners as well.60 Amenhotep II was not alone in perpetrating humiliating brutalities upon his enemies. During Merneptah’s reign, Libyan captives were “impaled to the south of Memphis, destroyed…carried off to Egypt and fire was hurled against their multitude in the presence of their relatives (?). (As to) the remainder, their hands were cut off because of their crimes, and others had eyes and ears removed.”61 Nubian prisoners of war were also impaled during Akhenaton’s reign, suggesting that “it was a regular feature of the punishments meted out to Egypt’s defeated enemies” (Schulman 1988, 92). Significantly, these spectacles of triumph were intended primarily for a domestic audience. Captives were usually brought back to Egypt to be executed, providing a public display of victory, royal power, and justice.62 Clearly, the torture and execution of enemies was in no way considered legally or morally problematic by Egyptian society. The inextricable connection between military victory and the restoration of Ma’at necessitated that the triumphal ritual demonstrated “the total abnegation of the opponent, not merely his submission but as well his destruction” (Spalinger 2013, 117).

The vulnerability of prisoners of war was underlined by the fact that they ceased to possess juridical status. Slightly different terminology described captives from independent territories and captives considered as domestic rebels, but both terms can be translated as meaning “like one who had never existed.”63 Enslavement brought humiliation and forced labor, as well as possibly torture and ritual execution. The binding, branding, and recording of prisoners of war was supervised by the “herald of captures” (Ziskind 1967, 151). The description of captives as dehumanized chattels is nowhere more striking than in a papyrus from the reign of Ramses IV (1153–1147 BCE). This text records that prisoners were “branded and made into slaves, they being stamped by my name, their women and children being dealt with likewise. I brought their herds to the House of Amun, they being made for him as cattle forever.”64

The enslavement of prisoners of war has largely been eliminated from the practice of modern warfare. Nonetheless, the current refusal to grant juridical status to non-state enemy combatants is perhaps not as far removed from Egyptian practice as one might wish. The abuse of detainees at Guantánamo Bay or Abu Ghraib prison, and the various torture techniques employed against them, evinces a degradation of human rights based on a refusal to grant juridical status to captured enemies.6566Yoo and Ho (2003, 209–22) argue that interstate terrorism should be classified as proper war under international law, yet insist that terrorists remain illegal combatants and thus enjoy none of the protections provided under the Geneva Conventions.67 Like prisoners-of-war taken by the ancient Egyptians, non-state combatants in the twenty-first century find themselves in a legal vacuum. Arguably, prisoners who are stripped of juridical status are also dispossessed of part of their individual human identity. It is hardly surprising that such prisoners should also experience a degradation of their humanity.68

Of all the motifs of Egyptian art depicting violence, the image of the pharaoh executing prisoners of war—“smiting his enemies”—was both the oldest and the most enduring. It was used from Predynastic times all the way up to the late Roman period: a span of over 3,500 years.69 The earliest discernible smiting scene is a painting from a Predynastic Tomb at Hierakonpolis (c. 3400 BCE), showing three bound prisoners kneeling before a chief/king who wields a mace raised in his right hand.70 A much more developed image is rendered on the famous Narmer Palette (Figure 1). King Narmer is depicted in what would become the stereotypical smiting pose: right arm raised and wielding a mace—ready to deliver the death blow—as his left hand grasps a kneeling prisoner by the hair. The intimate link between these scenes of ritual slaughter and the concept of justice was reinforced by the prominence of representations of Ma’at as a recurring feature of the iconography.71 The smiting scene was intended to represent the physical and symbolic defense of Ma’at and the defeat of Isfet (chaos). It was the quintessential act of justice.

Egyptian queens are occasionally depicted accompanying the pharaoh during the smiting ritual (Schoske 1982, 84–171), but in general women and children feature very rarely in the smiting scenes.72 This was a product of the patriarchal nature of Egyptian warfare and iconographic conventions rather than a recognition of non-combatant immunity. Depicting the pharaoh triumphing over women and children did little to enhance the king’s martial status. Equally, in representing the victory of good (pharaoh) over evil (enemy soldiers), women and children were superfluous to the needs of the scene.73 Nonetheless, female captives were a valuable element of military booty and were forced to endure the usual sexual exploitation suffered by women caught up in wars over the centuries. The Israelite Deuteronomic code may have attempted to bestow a very small measure of protection for female captives (Dt. 21:10–14), but there is no evidence for any equivalent rule in Egypt.74

There remains disagreement among Egyptologists whether the smiting scenes depict real or fictive violence.75 I believe that the sheer frequency and longevity of the smiting motif suggests that the ritual execution of prisoners was far more than artistic symbolism, and that executions were not abandoned in later periods. Political imagery must remain more closely aligned to reality than other types of imagery, exactly because it serves as a projection of power and intends to be convincing. Images can quickly lose their potency if unsupported by concrete power and action, as witnessed in the vandalism and destruction of political statuary in former Soviet states after 1989, or in Iraq after the toppling of Saddam Hussein’s regime in 2003. Arguably, ritual execution must have survived in Egypt as a royal practice (at least an occasional one) in order for the images to have retained any meaningful relevance and authority over several millennia.

That a civilization capable of incredible cultural and technological achievements should indulge in ritual murder undoubtedly creates an uncomfortable paradox for modern sensibilities. Of course, such paradoxes are commonplace in the histories of complex societies. In ancient Rome, the execution of prisoners of war was a feature of military triumphs, although its frequency is contested.76 In Mesoamerica, very large numbers of prisoners of war—male and female—were sacrificed in both Mayan and Aztec societies; the evisceration and decapitation of the victim played a central ritualistic and theological role.77 The Nuremberg executions of high-ranking Nazis in 1946, or the widely publicized use of beheading by Islamic extremists in Iraq since 2003 and by Islamic State since 2014, share a number of characteristics with the killing of military captives in ancient Egypt, Rome, or Mesoamerica. While the specific religious, cultural, and legal dimensions of this act vary considerably, it often goes hand-in-hand with absolutist views regarding enemy culpability. Furthermore, the essential purpose was, and is, consistent. Executing prisoners of war communicates a message of power, justice (however conceived), and retribution to a supportive audience (human or divine). At the same time, it communicates a threat of power, vengeance, and humiliation to the enemy. Seen in this broader chronological and geographical perspective, the execution of prisoners of war should be recognized as a normative feature of the historical practice and ethics of warfare.

Destruction of Property

The pharaoh’s de iure right to preserve or destroy enemy captives was extended to enemy property. During campaigns, the Egyptian army either consumed or looted movable property. Immovable property was prone to destruction, and campaign records testify to the deliberate targeting of agricultural resources, both cereal and arboreal.78 Egyptian armies had employed ravaging since at least Dynasty VI (c. 2345–2181 BCE), as described in the Autobiography of Weni:

This army returned in safety [henceforth refrain],

 It had ravaged the sand-dwellers’ land [Syria-Palestine].

[refrain]

 It had flattened the sand-dwellers’ land.

[refrain]

 It had sacked its strongholds.

[refrain]

 It had cut down its figs, its vines.

[refrain]

 It had thrown fire in all its (mansions).

[refrain]

 It had slain its troops by many ten thousands.

[refrain]

 (It had carried) off many (troops) as captives.79

This inscription from a private tomb tells us a number of things about how Egyptian commanders (and their descendants) assessed military success. The safe return of the army is entwined with the devastation inflicted upon the enemy’s territory. This destruction (certainly exaggerated here) was obviously intrinsic to the campaign’s success. Weni and his family were clearly proud of his achievements, so much so that they sought to preserve them for eternity in his tomb. Weni’s actions also gained the approval of his superiors: “His majesty praised me for it beyond anything. His majesty sent me to lead this army five times.”80 In short, there is no sense that discrimination or proportionality was required, and ruthlessness was rewarded with praise and additional military commands. From the campaigns of Weni to the English chevauchées of the Hundred Years’ War (1337–1453), or General Sherman’s infamous “March to the Sea” (1864), the objectives of these ravaging operations are comparable. Their purpose was to terrorize foes into submission, to destabilize the political authority of the opponent, to cripple an enemy’s economy in order to reduce military capability, and to acquire booty for the army.

Diplomacy

Neither universal nor particular immunities existed in Egyptian warfare. The concept of sanctuary or inviolable sacred space also seems to have been largely absent. This disregard for the enemy’s sacred space or objects probably resulted from notions of Egyptian religious superiority and the link between state gods and state wars. As it was believed that gods sanctioned the wars of political communities, gods (or rather, their temples) shared in the rewards of success but also the losses of defeat (Ziskind 1967, 143).

On the periphery of war, foreign envoys enjoyed guarantees for their safety and played a crucial role in negotiating formal international treaties. Evidence for such treaties originates in Egypt from at least the second millennium BCE but probably existed earlier. It includes defensive and offensive treaties as well as neutrality agreements.81 The gods acted as witnesses to treaties, and oaths were an essential component of the treaty-making process. To break one’s treaty oath was understood as both a political betrayal and a violation of the sacred. In consequence, “the aggrieved country and its pantheon were…entitled to utilize any means at their disposal to punish the offending country. This punishment included permitting or delegating the human ruler of the aggrieved country to make war” (Ziskind 1967, 126).

The best surviving example of an Egyptian peace treaty is that made between Ramses II and the Hittite king Hattusilis in 1280 BCE. Fortuitously, both the Egyptian and Hittite versions of the treaty have survived.82 The monarchs agreed upon a riksu (parity) treaty that was essentially a non-aggression pact as well as a defensive and offensive alliance between the two states. The rulers pledged “that good peace and brotherhood occur between us forever,” and this pledge was also incumbent upon their subjects.83

The Great Prince of Hatti shall not trespass against the land of Egypt forever, to take anything from it…the great ruler of Egypt, shall not trespass against the land (of Hatti, to take) from it forever…If another enemy come against the lands of User-maat-Re [Ramses II]…the Great Prince of Hatti shall (come to him and) the Great Prince of Hatti shall slay his enemy…But (if) another enemy (come) against the Great Prince (of Hatti), [Ramses II]…(shall) come to him as reinforcement to slay his enemy.84

The agreement to lend mutual military aid also encompassed military actions against rebellion in each country. Remarkably, the treaty specified that Egypt should send military aid to Hattusilis’s successors in the event of a royal succession crisis.85 This is perhaps the earliest example of formal conditions being agreed for an international military intervention. Finally, the treaty was witnessed by “a thousand gods of the male gods and of the female gods of them of the land of Hatti, together with a thousand gods of the male gods and of the female gods of them of the land of Egypt.” If either side violated the sacred contract, the gods of Hatti and Egypt would “destroy his house, his land, and his servants.”86

What this treaty shows is that ancient Egyptians conceived of war and peace as existing within a framework of divine and mundane international relations and law. Egyptians generally viewed hostile relations between states as less felicitous than peaceful relations, but war was an ethically and legally acceptable instrument of retribution, aggrandizement, and political control. Moreover, it was evidently a normal feature of New Kingdom international relations that future military ventures were subject to the obligations of treaties such as that between Ramses II and Hattusilis. Allies of Egypt could achieve a degree of legal symmetry, although the wording of the Egyptian version clearly portrays the Hittite king as inferior to the pharaoh.87 This treaty also shows that the Egyptian ethics of war, while distinctive, was not entirely sui generis. There were evidently a sufficient number of shared assumptions regarding the ethics and legalism of war that made this international treaty possible in the first place.

Conclusion

Taken as a whole, ancient Egyptian warfare operated within a well-established system of ethics; considerations of justice were fundamental to the Egyptian concept of righteous war. On the other hand, enemy “rights” were entirely absent from the Egyptian lexicon and prosecution of war. We have seen that it was normative to treat enemies with extreme brutality. Death on the battlefield as a combatant—or afterward as a prisoner of war—was to be expected, with rank offering little protection in this regard. Mutilation of enemy corpses was standard practice, fulfilling both monitory and administrative purposes. I find no evidence for limitations on weapons or tactics. All enemy property was a legitimate target, to be seized as booty or destroyed as part of a politico-military strategy to reduce enemy resources and inflict shock-and-awe intimidation. No meaningful distinctions were made between combatants and non-combatants in regard to property or persons. Women and children enjoyed no immunity. They, along with other enemy combatants and non-combatants, were enslaved on a grand scale. In sum, there appears to be almost nothing that could be identified as part of an ancient Egyptian ius in bello tradition. However, the absence of a ius in bello tradition was the direct consequence of the development of a prepotent ius ad bellum tradition.

Egypt’s vital cosmological role as a sanctuary and guardian of Ma’at amid a sea of chaos (Isfet) provided a powerful religious and political teleology upon which to establish an ethics of war. Wars that defended Egypt, a unique haven of order and truth, were intrinsically just. Egyptian royal ideology promoted the unequivocal authority of the quasi-divine pharaoh to wage war. Egyptian contempt for the “evil foreigner” endowed the state with an uncontested legitimacy to assert itself, reactively or proactively, against barbarism. Internal and external enemies were condemned as rebels and evildoers.

Reality, naturally, is infinitely more complex and fluid than images or texts can communicate. Ancient sources that were clearly intended to convey a variety of religious and political ideals pose numerous interpretative problems.88 It is no coincidence that Egyptian just war ideology, which stressed unity and authority around the person of the king, was promoted most vigorously during the periods of centralized monarchy. Yet the three major kingdom periods that I have examined were separated by prolonged “intermediate” periods marked by civil war, foreign occupation, and a fracturing of the Egyptian state into a number of competing territorial units. The Egyptian ethics of war developed, therefore, in conjunction with attempts to reinforce waxing or waning royal authority. Consequently, it is perhaps more a projection of political ideals than a reflection of political reality.

The precise historicity of representations of brutality in ancient Egyptian sources need not overly concern us when considering the ethics of war. What matters is that, for thousands of years, Egyptian elites wished to promote such actions as intrinsically “good.” Images of slaughter or enslavement of the enemy expressed ideals of warlike action. But the actual prosecution of Egyptian warfare may not have matched these ideal types. Egyptian military conduct was likely less brutal than the Egyptian ethics of war permitted. Not every town could be razed, not every enemy could or would be slaughtered, and it was not always politically astute to execute enemy leaders. The pragmatics and profits of war and politics undoubtedly erred toward at least some degree of restraint.89 The Egyptian-Hittite treaty demonstrates that Egyptian diplomacy and foreign policy was more sophisticated than mere brute force. Nonetheless, Egypt unleashed unlimited violence when it suited its purpose. Indeed, the defining feature of the Egyptian ethics of war is that, rather than being restrictive, it was highly permissive.

This important feature of ancient Egyptian military doctrine is not unique in the history of just war thought. Highly permissive doctrines emerged in other cultures in which absolute claims to justice—combined with universalizing politico-theological teleologies—shaped the process of legitimizing unlimited “just” force. Though it is misleading to frame Egyptian warfare in terms of a “religious crusade,”90 the medieval concept of holy war incorporated a comparable notion of universal justice (divine and natural) applying to all peoples (pagan and Christian). Prevailing doctrine rendered the defense of Christendom crucial to the salvation of humanity (Russell 1975, 112–26, 195–212). Christian holy war emerged initially as a justification for defending the Church against rebellion (that is, heresy), but by the mid-twelfth century Gratian could state uncontroversially that Christian prelates could exhort anyone to defend the faith against infidels.91 From the mid-thirteenth century, many canon lawyers insisted that Christians, infidels, and pagans were all under the universal jurisdiction of the pope (Brundage 1995a, 162–63). Thus, Christians and non-Christians alike were subject to the pope’s justice. However, canonists, theologians, and other medieval commentators placed very few limitations on the prosecution of wars in defense of the faith, resulting in warfare characterized by extreme brutality.92

The religious character of the Egyptian state, and the sharp distinction made between Egypt (governed by Ma’at) and foreign lands (ruled by Isfet), encourages comparison to medieval Islamic distinctions between the Dar al-Islam (House of Islam, that is, peace) and the Dar al-Harb (House of War). Like the pharaoh’s duty to maintain Ma’at, it was the duty of the Muslim head of state to maintain Islam.93 There are further parallels with radical interpretations of jihad that have emerged since the mid-twentieth century. Within Salafi jihadism, the focus on extreme claims to ius ad bellum has led to a complete abandonment of ius in bello limitations.94 The 1998 declaration of jihad released by Bin Laden’s World Islamic Front specifically states that “to kill the Americans and their allies—civilians and military—is an individual duty for every Muslim.”95 This interpretation of jihad, based on a stark distinction between “good” and “evil,” stands in contrast to more nuanced classical jihadist literature or more moderate modern interpretations.96

Perhaps the closest correlates to the Egyptian ethics of war appear in the ancient Roman concept of wars for survival (rather than for imperium or glory)97 and the ancient Israelite concept of Milhemit mitzvah (obligatory wars). The universalism of natural justice in the case of Rome, and the absolutism of divine justice in the case of Israel, permitted unlimited warfare as a counter to existential threats to the political community. For the Israelites, this was linked to the eschatological significance of Israel comprising the territory gifted by Yahweh to his chosen people. The biblical “ban” (herem) against a number of specific enemy communities residing within the promised land obligated the Israelites to engage in the genocidal killing of “everything that breathed,” including livestock.98 Egyptian doctrine differed from Israel and Rome in that all Egyptian wars could be conceived of in this extreme manner.

The aforementioned doctrines obviously differed significantly in content and detail. Yet we find marked similarities in their underlying assumptions. Whether rooted in cosmology, theology, or Stoic philosophy, each contains universalizing or absolutist notions of justice. These concepts of justice permitted military action against any and all deemed as transgressors against the law or threats to the community. Uniting all these doctrines was a definite sense of the enemy constituting a cultural “other”—often characterized as barbaric—against whom extreme violence was permissible.99

The wars of ancient Egypt are far removed from modern conflict. However, assumptions of, or claims to, universal or absolute justice in war are not consigned to the distant past or to the modern extremist fringe. As Morkevičius (2015, 13, 16–20) highlights, states display a tendency to “conflate national and universal conceptions of the good”; moreover, both realism and just war theory are grounded in assumptions of universality, pertaining either to the essential rationality of the state system or to the existence of universal moral norms.

Rengger (2013, 1–2, 8–9, 31–35, 106, 158–79) critiques the modern amalgamation of the just war as a punitive instrument to combat injustice with concepts of the liberal democratic state as an “enterprise association united around a notion of the common good,” thereby embodying “enlightened government” and justice. This has resulted in a less restrictive use of force in international politics. “Where injustice is everywhere, the reasons to use force to oppose it are not hard to find” (Rengger 2013, 67).

The conviction that the liberal democratic state and its concept of justice must be defended is made all the more necessary by the vivification of the state as a moral person, fully endowed with a conception of the good. Eckert (2009, 162, 174) goes so far as to argue that “aggression against a state is akin to murder” and that this “grounds the right to national defense.” On the other hand, the post–World War II era has also witnessed a growing emphasis on individual human rights, international humanitarian law, and the duty of states to defend against human rights abuses (for example, UN 1948).100 Since the end of the Cold War, the UN Security Council has been willing “to define ‘threats to the peace’ more broadly and flexibly” than simple violations of territorial sovereignty.101 This, in turn, increases the likelihood of military interventions on humanitarian grounds—often in violation of claims to state sovereignty. Stromseth, Wippman, and Brooks (2006, 5, 9) observe that this “new interventionism will probably be a feature of the global order for years to come,” and is usually justified on the basis of instating or reinstating the “rule of law.” They (2006, 1–17) also highlight that the humanitarian or security concerns motivating interventions have led to these operations being characterized as a form of “new imperialism” or “liberal imperialism.”

The authors (2006, 55) assert that “building the rule of law after intervention depends on strengthening cultural commitments to—and public confidence in—the very idea of law.” Yet the authors neglect the fact that Western liberal democratic states dominated the creation and promotion of a universal idea and rule of law through the United Nations. In consequence, the concept of international law broadly reflects Western liberal cultural values and requirements, while lacking full cognizance of cultural differences.102 Universally applicable “law” has become synonymous with Western liberal democratic principles of law. When the authors claim that interventions must strengthen the idea and rule of law, what they really mean is that interveners must establish Western liberal democratic law. Thus, the imposition of the “rule of law” through interventionism constitutes, in itself, a form of legal-cultural imperialism. These assumptions and objectives are, somewhat ironically, more than a little reminiscent of the ancient Egyptian attitude to universal justice and law.

Uncompromising interpretations of justice, combined with the veneration of a singular political order, can produce sophisticated and powerful just war doctrines. However, the conviction that justice and war are interrelated clearly offers no guarantee that the destructiveness of war will be reduced. Indeed, it may in fact make war more destructive. In this regard, ancient Egyptian thought on war prefigures some later developments in the West and Middle East.103 This is also relevant to the relationship between justice and military necessity in contemporary conflicts; conceptions of justice directly impact upon the extent to which military necessity can exculpate collateral damage. The permissibility of abandoning rules of restraint—especially non-combatant immunity—in order to serve military necessity is alive in Walzer’s (2006, 251–68) well-known argument for “Supreme Emergency.”

More recently, Crawford (2003, 4–12, 160–75; 2013, 235–41, 245) forcefully demonstrated how the modern just war tradition, international law, and military practitioners have accommodated military necessity as a means to permit the moral and lawful harming of civilians. Collateral damage is excused as the “inevitable” unintended consequence of necessary and proportionate military actions. US military operations in Afghanistan, Pakistan, and Iraq rarely intentionally target civilians, but Crawford shows that not all cases of collateral damage are simply tragic accidents. Foreseeable civilian casualties have frequently been permitted as an acceptable cost for achieving military objectives or enhancing force protection. Military necessity therefore becomes “a synonym for military utility” (Crawford 2003, 175).

If governments and their publics are convinced of the justice of a particular war—without accepting the possibility of ambiguities over issues such as just cause or enemy culpability—then the success of military operations, regardless of the “unintended” costs to civilians, becomes an overriding priority. It is easy to imagine how an ever more expansive interpretation of military necessity would be directly proportional to the perceived importance of obtaining victory against an absolutely unjust enemy.

This article has demonstrated that complex thought about war and justice is not unique to the West or to Christianity. I argued that we must expand the history of the just war tradition to recognize the rich seam of just war thought that existed in ancient Egypt, well before the advent of Greco-Roman, Judeo-Christian, or Islamic considerations of this topic. Furthermore, I have highlighted how ancient Egyptian just war thought shares certain characteristics with later classical, medieval, and even contemporary doctrines.

An understanding of the past should help inform the just war doctrine of the present. The ancient Egyptian ethics of war demonstrates that absolute judgments in the realms of morality or justice intensify the destructive nature of war in both its conceptualization and prosecution. The challenge for contemporary just war doctrine is to create an ethical and legal framework that is robust enough to permit and regulate military force under pressing and determinable circumstances, yet flexible enough to accommodate the reality that, in something as complex as war, there are very few absolute truths.

Supplementary Information

Supplemental Information is available at the International Studies Quarterly Data Archive.

Rory Cox is Lecturer in Late Medieval History at the University of St. Andrews, and a Fellow of the Royal Historical Society. Associate Director of the Institute of Intellectual History, St. Andrews: http://www.intellectualhistory.net. His research focuses on the history of the just war tradition and military conduct, from antiquity to the present day.

1

For Greek and Roman just war thought: Ober (1994); Bellamy (2006, 15–20); Reichberg, Syse, and Begby (2006, 3–59); Syse (2006, 2010); Lanni (2008); Neff (2008, 13–38); Raymond (2010); Cox (2015, 2–4); O’Driscoll (2015). Nevertheless, the focus remains fixed on the West. Some, notably Kelsay (1993, 2003, 2006, 2007, 2010), have attempted to incorporate non-Western traditions into the debate. See also the collections of comparative essays in Johnson and Kelsay (1990), Kelsay and Johnson (1991), Brekke (2006), and Hensel (2010).

2

For further discussion, see Supplemental Information: Appendix 1, “Egyptian Culture and the West.”

3

Dates should be taken as approximate. The dating of Egyptian dynastic periods and the reign lengths of pharaohs remains subject to debate: I have followed the date system used in Morkot (2010).

4

See Supplemental Information: Appendix 2, “Note on Ancient Egyptian Warfare.”

5

Munn-Rankin (1956); Ziskind (1967, 43–44, 203). The attempt to reconstruct an ancient Near Eastern legal system goes back to Selden (1640). For subsequent early attempts, see Ziskind (1967, 2–3). For the legal-diplomatic systems of Egypt and other Near Eastern powers, see Korošec (1931), Ziskind (1967), Pritchard (1969, 159–223; 2011, 150–225), Bederman (2001, 16–31, 137–54), Westbrook (2003).

6

See Supplemental Information: Appendix 3, “Ancient Egyptian Ethics of War: A Brief Historiographical Outline.”

7

The ancient Egyptians would not have recognized terms such as ius ad bellum and ius in bello. They are used here simply to highlight how Egyptian concepts and practices articulated values that bear direct comparison to features of the later just war tradition.

8

The precise nature of the pharaoh’s divinity remains a subject of debate. Earlier scholarship tended to emphasize the divinity of the pharaoh (Frankfort 1948, 24–47; 143–212); however, some recent scholarship (Posener 1960; Hornung 1983, 139–42; Baines 1995, 6, 9) has stressed the pharaoh’s human attributes. Nonetheless, some scholars remain willing to refer to the “deified ruler” (Silverman 1995, 72, 80, 85, 87; Menu 2003, 55), especially Amenhotep III and Ramses II.

9

Berlin 3029 in Lichtheim (1973:1, 117).

10

“La guerre est à la fois un moyen, pour le roi, de remplir ses obligations à l’égard de ses sujets, et une valorisation de ses fonctions, de son statut de roi-dieu.” My translation.

11

This was certainly practiced during and after the New Kingdom and was probably practiced much earlier: Baines (1995, 23); Gnirs and Loprieno (2009, 249); Spalinger (2013, 97).

12

Carnarvon Tablet I in Pritchard (1969, 232–33).

13

Poetical Stela of Merneptah in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 75); cf. Pritchard (1969, 376–78).

14

Poetical Stela of Thutmose III in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 36). See also Tale of Sinuhe: Parkinson (2009, 38); Lichtheim (1973, 2, 41).

15

Menu (2003, 51) describes Ma’at as “le clé du système institutionnel de l’Égypte pharaonique” and defines it thus: “‘l’ensemble des conditions qui font naître et qui renouvellent la vie’ ou, plus brièvement, le ‘principe de vie’, autrement dit: l’ordre, l’équité, la justice, la vérité, mais aussi la prosperité et la victoire, tandis qu’isfet en est l’antithèse: le chaos, l’injustice, le mensonge, la misère, la défaite, les ennemis, en un mot tous les éléments mortifères.” On the concept of Ma’at, see Assmann (1990); Karenga (2004); Goebs (2007, 275–81). On the cosmological superiority of Egypt, see Gnirs (1999, 72–73); O’Connor (2003, 160–61).

16

During Dynasty V, c. 2498–2345 BCE (Lichtheim 1997, 19).

17

The Words of Nerferti in Parkinson (2009, 136–37); cf. Lichtheim (1973, 1, 139–45). For similar themes, see The Words of Khakheperreseneb in Parkinson (2009, 144–50); The Admonitions of Ipuwer in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 152); and Parkinson (2009, 173).

18

The Words of Nerferti in Parkinson (2009, 139); cf. Instructions to King Merikare in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 105).

19

Lichtheim (1997, 36–37, 46); David (2013, 17–19).

20

See Tale of the Eloquent Peasant in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 169–84) and Parkinson (2009, 54–88); Dialogue of a Man with His Soul (Ba) in Parkinson (2009, 158–89).

21

Plato (1968, bk. 5, 470c–e, 471a–b); Aristotle (1998, bk. 7, 1333b.37–1334a.10).

22

Hymn IV to Senusret (Sesostris) III in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 200). Gnirs and Loprieno (2009, 247) highlight the continuities in Old, Middle, and New Kingdom militaristic literature by noting the similarities in structure and phraseology between this hymn, the Autobiography of Weni (below, n. 79), and the Poetical Stela of Thutmose III (above, n. 14; below, n. 27, n. 34).

23

Carnarvon Tablet I in Pritchard (1969, 232).

24

Poetical Stela of Merneptah in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 76).

25

See The Autobiography of Ahmose son of Abana in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 13).

26

Annals of Thutmose III in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 30).

27

Poetical Stela of Thutmose III in Lichtheim (1973 2, 37).

28

North exterior wall of great hypostyle hall at Karnak, in Pritchard (1969, 254).

29

See Hymn I to Senusret III in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 198–99); Tale of Sinuhe in Parkinson (2009, 30).

30

See Stelae of Amenhotep II in Pritchard (1969, 245); Barkal Stela in Pritchard (1969, 240); Kadesh Bulletin and the Kadesh Poem in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 57–72); examples of the Kadesh battle reliefs in Seidel and Schulz (2005, 322, 371).

31

Muhlestein (2011, 83) describes the non-Egyptian foreigner as “the prototypical rebel.”

32

Lorton (1977, 14, 26, 28–31, 34–36); Jasnow (2003b, 281–82; 2003c, 242–46); Muhlestein (2008, 2011, 34–43, 79–82); Janzen (2013, 250–59). Lorton (1977, 15, 51) disputes burning as a capital punishment prior to the Late Period—a position convincingly challenged by Leahy (1984, 199–202) and Muhlestein (2008, 192–94). For an overview of ancient Egyptian law, see Jasnow (2003a, 2003b, 2003c).

33

From two speeches of Senusret I, cited in Redford (1995, 165); see also Muhlestein (2008, 189–93; 2011, 37–39); Janzen (2013, 304–5).

34

Lichtheim (1973, 2, 14); Armant Stela in Pritchard (1969, 234); cf. Annals of Thutmose III and Poetical Stela of Thutmose III in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 29–39).

35

Memphis and Karnak Stelae of Amenhotep II in Pritchard (1969, 245–46).

36

Kadesh Poem in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 70).

37

“When the time of breakfast had come, I attacked him. I broke down his walls, I killed his people, and I made his wife come down to the riverbank.” Carnarvon Tablet I in Pritchard (1969, 233); cf. Spalinger (2005, 3, 16). Declarations of war were common in other ancient Near Eastern societies (Ziskind 1967, 125–37; Bederman 2001, 208–41).

38

Instructions to Merikare in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 103–4).

39

Victory Stela of King Piye in Lichtheim (1973, 3, 69). Piye, a non-Egyptian Kushite invader, still appealed to traditional Egyptian ideas of military legitimacy by claiming that his campaign was inspired by Amun-Re (Baines 1995, 36).

40

Pritchard (1969, 328–29); Shaw (1991, 9); Ritner (1993, 136–80); Hamblin (2006, 348, 415–18); Muhlestein (2008, 194–96; 2011, 19–20); Janzen (2013, 18–21, 314–17); (Bryan etal. 2015, 22).

41

Strabo (10.448) and Polybius (13.3.2–4) report that during the War of Lelantine Plain, on the island of Euboea (c. 700 BCE), the belligerents banned projectile weapons. There is some doubt as to the historicity of these reports: Wheeler (1987); Ober (1994, 12–13); Lanni (2008, 471); and O’Driscoll (2015, 5). The Second Lateran Council (1179) attempted to ban the use of bows and crossbows in wars between Christians: Concilium Lateranenses II, Canon 29, in Alberigo etal. (1973, 203).

42

Hamblin (2006, 32); McDermott (2004, 151–57). Images: Epigraphic Survey (1986); Seidel and Schulz (2005, 124, 322, 324, 375). Despite Egyptian enemies being referred to as “Bowmen” (Iwntyw) (Lichtheim 1973, 1, 115), which might lead us to expect a pejorative connotation with archery, one of the honorary titles of the pharaoh was “Mighty of Bows in All Lands”: Stelae of Seti I in Pritchard (1969, 253); Tale of Sinuhe in Parkinson (2009, 30); Kadesh Poem in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 62–63). See also Appendix 2.

43

Ziskind (1967, 140–41). Compare the permissive attitude of Augustine and medieval canon law: Gratian (1879, Causa 23, q. 2, canon 2).

44

The story has obvious parallels to the later Homeric story of the Trojan Horse. Gnirs and Loprieno (2009, 263–64) observe the relationship between this “historical” military anecdote and contemporary Egyptian literary tales.

45

Teaching for King Merikare in Parkinson (2009, 223); Lichtheim (1973, 1, 103–4, 119). Cf. Lorton (1973, 65–8) for the translation of xsy as “weak”/“defeated” rather than the pejoratives “miserable”/“wretched”/“vile.”

46

Lichtheim (1973, 1, 119).

47

Ideological sources may not reflect the reality of interactions with foreigners: O’Connor (2003).

48

Autobiography of Ahmose in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 14).

49

Barkal Stela in Pritchard (1969, 240). See also Kamose’s sack of Nefrusi: Pritchard (1969, 233).

50

These attitudes and conventions were also incorporated into literary works, for example The Tale of Sinuhe in Parkinson (2009, 32).

51

“[V]iol[ator of the] Babylonian [woman], the Byblian maid, the little girl of Alalakh and the old crone of Arrapkha!” Cited in Redford (1992, 230). For enemy soldiers being compared to women in Egyptian texts, see Gnirs and Loprieno (2009, 250–52).

52

Lanni (2008, 473, 478–79); O’Driscoll (2015, 7).

53

For analysis of the Narmer Palette and other Archaic Period ritual slayings, see Muhlestein (2011, 9–15).

54

Lorton (1974b, 53, 60).

55

Autobiography of Ahmose in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 12–13, 33–34).

56

Cited in Schulman (1988, 90–91, n. 122); see also Cline and O’Connor (2003, 135). The removal of phalli was probably linked to the emasculation of dead foes (Gnirs and Loprieno 2009, 252).

57

Biography of Amenemheb in Pritchard (1969, 241); Autobiography of Ahmose in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 13). Cf. Lorton (1974a, 1974b) for New Kingdom practice.

58

The brutal treatment of foreign captives during the New Kingdom is explored in Janzen (2013).

59

Stelae of Amenhotep II in Temples of Amada and Elephantine, in Pritchard (1969, 248); see also Spalinger (2013, 99).

60

Pritchard (1969, 247); see also Janzen (2013, 251–55). On the connection between burning and rebellion in Egyptian legal thought, see Leahy (1984, 200–203); Muhlestein (2008, 187).

61

Merneptah Year 4, Amada stela, cited in Schulman (1988, 91–92); Trigger etal. (1983, 238).

62

Spalinger (2013, 99) comments on Amenhotep II’s hanging of the Syrian chiefs: “The reason for this often presumed ‘barbaric activity’ was simple…it was Amunhotep’s wish to demonstrate visually his success.”

63

Lorton (1974b, 54). The same Egyptian terms were applied to persons and plunder (like of cattle), thus emphasizing prisoners as chattel property (Lorton 1974b, 55–56, 62).

64

Papyrus Harris, cited in McDermott (2004, 118).

66

Dratel (2005, xxi) observes that the abuse of prisoners in Afghanistan, Guantánamo Bay, and Iraq was the product of: “(1) the desire to place the detainees beyond the reach of any court or law; (2) the desire to abrogate the Geneva Convention with respect to the treatment of persons seized in the context of armed hostilities.” On the US government’s efforts to separate enemy combatants from normal legal process and protections, and the expansion of the use of torture by the CIA in the “War against Terrorism,” see CIA (2004); Greenberg and Dratel (2005); Hersh (2005, 1–72); Blakeley (2011).

67

Discussed by Frowe (2016, 205–22).

68

This dehumanizing effect is recognized by the title and content of the United Nations’ Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (UN 1984).

69

See Seton (1971, 1–113); Śliwa (1974, 98–105); Wildung (1977, 114–17); Schoske (1982); Ritner (1993, 113–19); Müller-Wollerman (2009, 49–56); Zimmerman (2013, 73–75).

70

A scene found on a C-ware vessel (c. 3600 BCE) depicts a large figure who appears to hold a mace-like object in one hand and a much smaller captive in the other (Muhlestein 2011, 85). While the scene is suggestive of later smiting iconography, it cannot be identified definitely as a smiting scene.

71

See Schoske (1982, 84–171).

72

Reliefs from the pyramid complex of Sahure (2487–2475 BCE) depict two children and a woman crouching behind the foot of the victim—possibly his wife and children: Seton (1971, 7–9).

73

On enemies being compared to women as an insult, see above, n. 51.

74

The Deuteronomic stipulations were probably only intended to apply to intertribal conflicts rather than foreign wars (Ziskind 1967, 152).

75

See Supplemental Information: Appendix 4, “The Historicity of Ancient Egyptian Smiting Scenes.”

76

Compare Kyle (1998, 217) to Beard (2007, 128–32). The comparison with Rome is also made by Schulman (1988, 46) and Janzen (2013, 289–96). On Roman uses of extreme violence, see Zimmerman (2013, 219–339). For a comparative view of triumphal celebration rituals in the ancient Mediterranean world, see essays in Spalinger and Armstrong (2013).

77
78

Annals of Thutmose III in Pritchard (1969, 238–39); Annals of Thutmose III in Lichtheim (1973, 2, 33). Deuteronomy stipulated that fruit trees should be preserved when besieging an enemy city (Dt. 20:19), evidence of their high value.

79

Autobiography of Weni in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 20).

80

Autobiography of Weni in Lichtheim (1973, 1, 20).

81

Munn-Rankin (1956, 99–102, 107–8); Ziskind (1967, 66–120); Shaw (1991, 45); O’Connor (2003, 168). On diplomatic immunity and treaty practices in the ancient Near East and Mediterranean, see Bederman (2001, 88–136, 137–206).

82

The Egyptian and Hittite versions are printed in Pritchard (1969, 199–203). The Hittite Empire flourished between c. 1600–1150 BCE and occupied much of what is now modern-day Turkey, Syria, and Lebanon.

83

Pritchard (1969, 199, 200); cf. Hittite text, ibid., 202.

85

Pritchard (1969, 202–3).

86

Pritchard (1969, 200–203). David (2013, 16, 19) highlights this as a further example of the Egyptian concept of retributive justice in practice.

87

Above, n. 82.

88

For discussion, see Cifola (1988, 276–77); Shaw (1991, 9); O’Connor (2003); Cline and O’Connor (2003, 120–32); and Baines (1996, 349–52).

89

See O’Connor (2003, 166, 168–69).

90

As McDermott (2004, 85) attempts. Ziskind (1967, 131–36, 153) warns against the anachronism of applying the term “holy war” to the ancient Near East, while Muhlestein (2011, 7) highlights that state and religion cannot be separated in ancient Egypt. Egyptian wars were not proselytizing (O’Connor 2003, 166), and Egyptian theology was markedly different to Christian concepts of heaven, hell, sin, and forgiveness. Such concepts were the theological underpinnings of the penitential commutations and indulgences (indulgentia) that helped fuel and later to define the crusade movement. See Brundage (1976, 1995b); Bachrach (2003, 108–50).

91

See Gratian (1879, Causa 23, prologue; q. 3, canons 1–11; q. 4, canon 25, dicta post canonum [d.p.c.] 29, d.p.c. 30; q. 6; q. 7; q. 8, d.p.c. 6, d.p.c. 28).

92

Medieval lawyers categorized unlimited holy war as bellum Romanum, ‘Roman wars”: Russell (1975, 195–212); Brundage (1976, 118, 122–25). For examples of brutality, see Cox (2012, 118–21).

93

Montgomery Watt (1976, 152). Al-Qaeda have asserted new models of legitimate authority to declare jihad: Zehr (2013, 99–100, 101–5).

94

Kelsay (1993, 69–74, 100–110); Bonner (2008, 157–65); Brachman (2009); Zehr (2013, 98).

96

For example, Peters (1977); Kelsay (2003, 2006); Al-Tabari (2007); Al-Sistani (2015). Thanks to Ahab Bdaiwi for bringing Al-Sistani’s rules to my attention. Unlike in Islam, Egyptian warfare was not accompanied by a sense of spiritual struggle (the “greater jihad”).

97

Cicero (2009, 16–17).

98

Bederman (2001, 209–12); Van Wees (2010, 242). See Deut. 20:16–17; 13:12–16; Num. 31:14–18; Jos. 6:20–21; 8:2, 27; 11:14; 1 Sam. 15:3. For a medieval Jewish interpretation of this obligation, see Feldman (2006, 94–99).

99

See above, n. 21, n. 92.

100

Cosmopolitan theorists such as Kaldor (2007) and Fabre (2008, 2012) argue that traditional ideas of state authority are no longer relevant for the “new wars” of the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries. Kaldor’s (2007, 193) suggestion that authority for the defense of global human rights should be passed to transnational bodies is, as she admits, based on the belief that “public morality has to be underpinned by universalist projects.”

101

Stromseth, Wippman, and Brooks (2006, 18–55, quoted text at 32).

102

Puchala (2005, 572–75, 577, 580–82).

103

Whether any influence existed between ancient Egyptian and later Western and Islamic thought must remain moot at present. A systematic comparison is beyond the scope of this article, but the author is working on just such a comparative project.

References

Alberigo
Josepho
,
Dossetti
Josepho A.
,
Joannu
Perikle
,
Leonardi
Claudio
,
Prodi
Paulo
, eds.
1973
.
Conciliorum Oecumenicorum Decreta
. 3rd ed.
Bologna
:
Istitutio per le Scienze Religiose
.

Al-Sistani
Al-Sayyid Ali Al-Husseini.
2015
. “Advice and Guidance to the Fighters on the Battlefields.” Accessed December 10, 2015. http://www.sistani.org/english/archive/25036/.

Al-Tabari
.
2007
.
Al-Tabari’s Book of Jihad: A Translation from the Original Arabic, with an Introduction, Commentary, and Notes by Y. S. Ibrahim
.
Lewiston, NY and Lampeter, UK
:
Edwin Mellen Press
.

Aristotle
.
1998
.
The Politics
, translated by
Everson
S.
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Assmann
Jan.
1990
.
Ma’at: Gerechtigkeit und Unsterblichkeit im alten Ägypten
.
Munich
:
C. H. Beck
.

Bachrach
David S.
2003
.
Religion and the Conduct of War c. 300–1215
.
Woodbridge
:
Boydell
.

Baines
John.
1995
. “Kingship, Definition of Culture, and Legitimation.” In
Ancient Egyptian Kingship
, edited by
O’Connor
David
,
Silverman
David P.
,
3
47
.
Leiden, New York, and Köln
:
Brill
.

Baines
John.
1996
. “Contextualizing Egyptian Representations of Society and Ethnicity.” In
The Study of the Ancient Near East in the Twenty-First Century: The William Foxwell Albright Centennial Conference
, edited by
Cooper
Jerrold S.
,
Schwartz
Glenn M.
,
339
84
.
Winona Lake, IN
:
Eisenbrauns
.

Beard
Mary.
2007
.
The Roman Triumph
.
Cambridge, MA, and London
:
Harvard University Press
.

Bederman
David J.
2001
.
International Law in Antiquity
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Bellamy
Alex J.
2006
.
Just Wars: From Cicero to Iraq
.
Cambridge
:
Polity Press
.

Berryman
Carrie Anne.
2007
. “Captive Sacrifice and Trophy Taking Among the Ancient Maya: An Evaluation of the Bioarchaeological Evidence and Its Sociopolitical Implications.” In
The Taking and Displaying of Human Body Parts as Trophies by Amerindians
, edited by
Chacon
Richard J.
,
Dye
David H.
,
377
99
.
New York
:
Springer
.

Black
Anthony.
2009
.
A World History of Ancient Political Thought
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Blakeley
Ruth.
2011
. “
Dirty Hands, Clean Conscience? The CIA Inspector General’s Investigation of ‘Enhanced Interrogation Techniques’ in the War on Terror and the Torture Debate
.”
Journal of Human Rights
10
4
:
544
61
.

Bonner
Michael.
2008
.
Jihad in Islamic History: Doctrines and Practice
.
Princeton, NJ, and Oxford
:
Princeton University Press
.

Brachman
Jarret M.
2009
.
Global Jihadism: Theory and Practice
.
Abingdon and New York
:
Routledge
.

Brekke
Torkel
, ed.
2006
.
The Ethics of War in Asian Civilizations: A Comparative Perspective
.
London
:
Routledge
.

Brundage
James A.
1976
. “Holy War and the Medieval Lawyers.” In
The Holy War
, edited by
Murphy
Thomas Patrick
,
99
140
.
Columbus
:
Ohio State University Press
.

Brundage
James A.
1995a
.
Medieval Canon Law
.
London and New York
:
Longman
.

Brundage
James A.
1995b
. “
The Hierarchy of Violence in Twelfth- and Thirteenth-Century Canonists
.”
International History Review
17
4
:
670
92
.

Bryan
Betsy
,
Walker
Roxie
,
Ikram
Salima
,
Irish
Joel
.
2015
. “Execration and Execution: A Skeleton of a Bound Captive from the Mut Temple Precinct.” In Paper and Poster Abstracts of the International Congress of Egyptologists XI, Florence (Italy), August 23–30, 2015. Accessed December 8, 2016. http://camnes.it/xi-international-congress-of-egyptologist.

Central Intelligence Agency (CIA)
.
2004
. “CIA Inspector General Special Review: Counterterrorism, Detention and Interrogation Activities (September 2001–October 2003).” Accessed March 24, 2016. https://fas.org/irp/cia/product/ig-interrog.pdf.

Chevereau
Pierre-Marie.
1999
.
“L’art et la science militaires dans l’Égypte ancienne.”
Stratégique (ISC)
74
5
. Accessed April 25, 2016. http://www.institut-strategie.fr/strat_7475_CHEVEREAU.html.

Cicero
Marcus Tullius.
2009
.
On Duties
, edited by
Griffin
M. T.
,
Atkins
E. M.
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Cifola
Barbara.
1988
. “
Ramses III and the Sea Peoples: A Structural Analysis of the Medinet Habu Inscriptions
.”
Orientalia
57
3
:
275
306
.

Cline
Eric H.
,
O’Connor
David
.
2003
. “The Mystery of the ‘Sea Peoples.’” In
Mysterious Lands
, edited by
O’Connor
David
,
Quirke
Stephen
,
107
38
.
London, UK, Portland, OR, and Coogee, Australia
:
UCL Press
.

Cox
Rory.
2012
. “
Asymmetric Warfare and Military Conduct in the Middle Ages
.”
Journal of Medieval History
38
1
:
100
125
.

Cox
Rory.
2015
. “The Ethics of War Up to Thomas Aquinas.” In
The Oxford Handbook of Ethics and War
, edited by
Lazar
Seth
,
Frowe
Helen
. Accessed December 8, 2016. http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199943418.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199943418-e-19.

Crawford
Neta C.
2003
.
Accountability for Killing: Moral Responsibility for Collateral Damage in America’s Post-9/11 Wars
.
New York
:
Oxford University Press
.

Crawford
Neta C.
2013
. “Bugsplat: US Standing Rules of Engagement, International Humanitarian Law, Military Necessity, and Noncombatant Immunity.” In
Just War: Authority, Tradition, and Practice
, edited by
Lang
Anthony F.
Jr.
,
O’Driscoll
Cian
,
Williams
John
,
231
49
.
Washington, DC
:
Georgetown University Press
.

David
Arlette.
2011
. “
Devouring the Enemy: Ancient Egyptian Metaphors of Domination
.”
Bulletin of the Australian Centre for Egyptology
22
:
83
100
.

David
Arlette.
2013
. “The Sound of the Magic Flute in Legal and Religious Registers of the Ramesside Period: Some Common Features of Two ‘Ritualistic Languages.’” In
Law and Religion in the Eastern Mediterranean: From Late Antiquity to Early Islam
, edited by
Hagedorn
Anselm C.
,
Kratz
Reinhard G.
,
13
39
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Dratel
Joshua L.
2005
. “The Legal Narrative.” In
The Torture Papers: The Road to Abu Ghraib
, edited by
Greenberg
Karen J.
,
Dratel
Joshua L.
,
xxi
xxiv
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Eckert
Amy E.
2009
. “
National Defense and State Personality
.”
Journal of International Political Theory
5
2
:
161
76
.

Epigraphic Survey
.
1986
.
The Battle Reliefs of King Sety I: Reliefs and Inscriptions at Karnak
, vol.
4
.
Chicago
:
Oriental Institute of the University of Chicago
.

Fabre
Cécile.
2008
. “
Cosmopolitanism, Just War Theory and Legitimate Authority
.”
International Affairs
84
5
:
963
76
.

Fabre
Cécile.
2012
.
Cosmopolitan War
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Feldman
Noah.
2006
. “War and Reason in Maimonides and Averroes.” In
The Ethics of War: Shared Problems in Different Traditions
, edited by
Sorabji
Richard
,
Rodin
David
,
92
107
.
Aldershot, UK
:
Ashgate
.

Frankfort
Henri.
1948
.
Kingship and the Gods: A Study of Ancient Near Eastern Religion as the Integration of Society and Nature
.
Chicago
:
University of Chicago Press
.

Frowe
Helen.
2016
.
The Ethics of War and Peace: An Introduction
.
Abingdon, UK, and New York
:
Routledge
.

Gnirs
Andrea M.
1999
. “Ancient Egypt.” In
War and Society in the Ancient and Medieval Worlds: Asia, The Mediterranean, Europe, and Mesoamerica
, edited by
Raaflaub
Kurt
,
Rosenstein
Nathan
,
71
104
.
Cambridge, MA, and London
:
Harvard University Press
.

Gnirs
Andrea M.
,
Loprieno
Antonio
.
2009
. “Krieg und Literatur.” In
Militärgeschichte des pharaonischen Ägypten: Altägypten und seine Nachbarkulturen im Spiegel der aktuellen Forschung
, edited by
Gundlach
Rolf
,
Vogel
Carola
,
243
308
.
Paderborn
:
Ferdinand Schöningh
.

Goebs
Katja.
2007
. “Kingship.” In
The Egyptian World
, edited by
Wilkinson
Toby
,
275
95
.
Abingdon, UK, and New York
:
Routledge
.

Gratian
.
1879
.
Decretum Magistri Gratiani, Corpus Iuris Canonici
, vol.
1
, edited by
Friedberg
Emil
.
Leipzig
:
Bernhard Tauchnitz
.

Greenberg
Karen J.
,
Dratel
Joshua L.
, eds.
2005
.
The Torture Papers: The Road to Abu Ghraib
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Hamblin
William J.
2006
.
Warfare in the Ancient Near East to 1600 BC: Holy Warriors at the Dawn of History
.
Abingdon, UK, and New York
:
Routledge
.

Hensel
Howard M.
, ed.
2010
.
The Prism of Just War: Asian and Western Perspectives on the Legitimate Use of Military Force
.
Farnham, UK, and Burlington, VT
:
Ashgate
.

Hersh
Seymour M.
2005
.
The Chain of Command: The Road from 9/11 to Abu Ghraib
.
New York
:
Harper Perennial
.

Hornung
Erik.
1983
.
Conceptions of God in Ancient Egypt: The One and the Many
, translated by
Baines
John
.
London
:
Routledge
.

Janzen
Mark D.
2013
. “The Iconography of Humiliation: The Depiction and Treatment of Bound Foreigners in New Kingdom Egypt.” PhD thesis, Memphis University. Accessed March 17, 2016. https://umwa.memphis.edu/etd/index.php/view/download/mjanzen/798/Janzen.pdf.

Jasnow
Richard.
2003a
. “Old Kingdom and First Intermediate Period.” In
A History of Ancient Near Eastern Law
, edited by
Westbrook
Raymond
,
93
140
.
Leiden and Boston
:
Brill
.

Jasnow
Richard.
2003b
. “Middle Kingdom and Second Intermediate Period.” In
A History of Ancient Near Eastern Law
, edited by
Westbrook
Raymond
,
255
88
.
Leiden and Boston
:
Brill
.

Jasnow
Richard.
2003c
. “New Kingdom.” In
A History of Ancient Near Eastern Law
, edited by
Westbrook
Raymond
,
289
359
.
Leiden and Boston
:
Brill
.

Johnson
James Turner.
1981
.
Just War Tradition and the Restraint of War
.
Princeton, NJ
:
Princeton University Press
.

Johnson
James Turner.
1984
.
Can Modern War Be Just
?
New Haven, CT
:
Yale University Press
.

Johnson
James Turner.
1999
.
Morality and Contemporary Warfare
.
New Haven, CT
:
Yale University Press
.

Johnson
James Turner.
2011
.
Ethics and the Use of Force: Just War in Historical Perspective
.
Farnham, UK, and Burlington, VT
:
Ashgate
.

Johnson
James Turner
,
Kelsay
John
, eds.
1990
.
Cross, Crescent, and Sword: The Justification and Limitation of War in Western and Islamic Tradition
.
New York and London
:
Greenwood Press
.

Kaldor
Mary.
2007
.
New and Old Wars
. 2nd ed.
Stanford
:
Stanford University Press
.

Karenga
Maulana.
2004
.
Maat, the Moral Ideal in Ancient Egypt: A Study in Classical African Ethics
.
New York
:
Routledge
.

Kelsay
John.
1993
.
Islam and War: A Study in Comparative Ethics
.
Louisville, KY
:
Westminster/John Knox Press
.

Kelsay
John.
2003
. “
Al-Shaybani and the Islamic Law of War
.”
Journal of Military Ethics
2
1
:
63
75
.

Kelsay
John.
2006
. “Islamic Tradition and the Justice of War.” In
The Ethics of War in Asian Civilizations: A Comparative Perspective
, edited by
Brekke
Torkel
,
81
110
.
Abingdon, UK, and New York
:
Routledge
.

Kelsay
John.
2007
.
Arguing the Just War in Islam
.
Cambridge, MA
:
Harvard University Press
.

Kelsay
John.
2010
. “
Just War, Jihad, and the Study of Comparative Ethics
.”
Ethics and International Affairs
24
3
:
227
38
.

Kelsay
John
,
Johnson
James Turner
, eds.
1991
.
Just War and Jihad: Historical and Theoretical Perspectives on War and Peace in Western and Islamic Traditions
.
New York
:
Greenwood Press
.

Koros˘ec
Viktor.
1931
.
Hethitische Staatsverträge. Ein Beitrag zu ihrer juristischen Wertung
.
Leipzig
:
Th. Weicher
.

Kyle
Donald G.
1998
.
Spectacles of Death in Ancient Rome
.
London
:
Routledge
.

Lanni
Adriaan.
2008
. “
The Laws of War in Ancient Greece
.”
Law and History Review
26
3
:
469
89
.

Leahy
Anthony.
1984
. “
Death by Fire in Ancient Egypt
.”
Journal of Economic and Social History of the Orient
27
2
:
199
206
.

Lichtheim
Miriam
, ed. and trans.
1973
.
Ancient Egyptian Literature: A Book of Readings
.
3
vols.
Berkeley and London
:
University of California Press
.

Lichtheim
Miriam.
1997
.
Moral Values in Ancient Egypt
.
Fribourg, Switzerland
:
University Press. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht
.

Lorton
David.
1973
. “
The So-Called ‘Vile’ Enemies of the King of Egypt (in the Middle Kingdom and Dyn. XVIII)
.”
Journal of the American Research Center in Egypt
10
:
65
70
.

Lorton
David.
1974a
.
The Juridical Terminology of International Relations in Egyptian Texts through Dynasty XVIII
.
Baltimore
:
Johns Hopkins University Press
.

Lorton
David.
1974b
. “
Terminology Related to the Laws of Warfare in Dynasty XVIII
.”
Journal of the American Research Center in Egypt
11
:
53
68
.

Lorton
David.
1977
. “
The Treatment of Criminals in Ancient Egypt: Through the New Kingdom
.”
Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient
20
1
:
2
64
.

McDermott
Bridget.
2004
.
Warfare in Ancient Egypt
.
Stroud, UK
:
Sutton
.

Mendoza
Rubén G.
2007
. “The Divine Gourd Tree: Tzompantli Skull Racks, Decapitation Rituals, and Human Trophies in Ancient Mesoamerica.” In
The Taking and Displaying of Human Body Parts as Trophies by Amerindians
, edited by
Chacon
Richard J.
,
Dye
David H.
,
400
443
.
New York
:
Springer
.

Menu
Bernadette.
2003
. “
La legitimation de la guerre dans l’idéologie pharaonique
.”
Revue Droit et Cultures
45
:
49
64
.

Montgomery Watt
W.
1976
. “Islamic Conceptions of the Holy War.” In
The Holy War
, edited by
Murphy
Thomas P.
,
141
56
.
Columbus
:
Ohio State University Press
.

Morkevičius
Valerie.
2015
. “
Power and Order: The Shared Logics of Realism and Just War Theory
.”
International Studies Quarterly
59
:
11
22
.

Morkot
Robert G.
2010
.
A to Z Ancient Egyptian Warfare
.
Plymouth
:
Scarecrow Press
.

Moser
Christopher L.
1973
. “
Human Decapitation in Ancient Mesoamerica
.”
Studies in Precolumbian Art and Archaeology
11
:
1
72
.

Muhlestein
Kerry.
2008
. “
Royal Executions: Evidence bearing on the Subject of Sanctioned Killing in the Middle Kingdom
.”
Journal of Economic and Social History of the Orient
51
2
:
181
208
.

Muhlestein
Kerry.
2011
.
Violence in the Service of Order: The Religious Framework for Sanctioned Killing in Ancient Egypt
.
Oxford
:
Archaeopress
.

Müller-Wollermann
Renate.
2009
. “Symbolische Gewalt im Alten Ägypten.” In
Extreme Formen von Gewalt in Bild und Text des Altertum
, edited by
Zimmermann
Martin
,
47
64
.
Munich
:
Herbert Utz
.

Munn-Rankin
J. Margaret.
1956
. “
Diplomacy in Western Asia in the Early Second Millennium B.C
.”
Iraq
18
1
:
68
110
.

Neff
Stephen C.
2008
.
War and the Law of Nations: A General History
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Ober
Josiah.
1994
. “Classical Greek Times.” In
The Laws of War: Constraints on Warfare in the Western World
, edited by
Howard
Michael
,
Andreopoulos
George J.
,
Shulman
Mark
,
12
26
.
New Haven, CT, and London
:
Yale University Press
.

O’Connor
David.
2003
. “Egypt’s Views of Others.”
In Never Had the Like Occurred: Egypt’s View of Its Past
, edited by
Tait
John
,
155
85
.
London
:
UCL Press
.

O’Driscoll
Cian.
2015
. “
Rewriting the Just War Tradition: Just War in Classical Greek Political Thought and Practice
.”
International Studies Quarterly
59
1
:
1
10
.

Parkinson
Richard B.
, trans.
2009
.
The Tale of Sinuhe and Other Ancient Egyptian Poems 1940–1640 BC
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Peters
Rudolph
, trans.
1977
.
Jihad in Medieval and Modern Islam: The Chapter on Jihad from Averroes’ Legal Handbook “Bidāyat al-Mudjtahid” and the Treatise “Koran and Fighting” by the Late Shaykh AlAzhar, Mahmūd Shaltūt
.
Leiden
:
Brill
.

Plato
.
1968
.
The Republic of Plato
, translated by
Bloom
A.
.
New York
:
Basic Books
.

Posener
Georges.
1960
.
De la divinité du Pharaon
.
Paris
:
Imprimerie Nationale
.

Pritchard
James B.
, ed.
1969
.
Ancient Near Eastern Texts Relating to the Old Testament
. 3rd ed. with supplement.
Princeton, NJ
:
Princeton University Press
.

Pritchard
James B.
2011
.
The Ancient Near East: An Anthology of Texts and Pictures
.
Princeton, NJ
:
Princeton University Press
.

Puchala
David.
2005
. “
World Hegemony and the United Nations
.”
International Studies Review
7
4
:
571
84
.

Raymond
Gregory A.
2010
. “The Greco-Roman Roots of the Just War Tradition.” In
The Prism of Just War: Asian and Western Perspectives on the Legitimate Use of Military Force
, edited by
Hensel
Howard M.
,
7
28
.
Farnham, UK, and Burlington, VT
:
Ashgate
.

Redford
Donald B.
1992
.
Egypt, Canaan, and Israel in Ancient Times
.
Princeton, NJ
:
Princeton University Press
.

Redford
Donald B.
1995
. “The Concept of Kingship during the Eighteenth Dynasty.” In
Ancient Egyptian Kingship
, edited by
O’Connor
David
,
Silverman
David P.
,
157
84
.
Leiden, New York, and Köln
:
Brill
.

Reichberg
Gregory M.
,
Syse
Henrik
,
Begby
Endre
, eds.
2006
.
The Ethics of War: Classic and Contemporary Readings
.
Malden, MA, and Oxford
:
Blackwell
.

Rengger
Nicholas.
2013
.
Just War and the International Order: The Uncivil Condition in World Politics
.
New York
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Ritner
Robert Kriech.
1993
.
The Mechanics of Ancient Egyptian Magical Practice
.
Chicago
:
Oriental Institute of the University of Chicago
. Accessed January 15, 2016. https://oi.uchicago.edu/sites/oi.uchicago.edu/files/uploads/shared/docs/saoc54_4th.pdf.

Russell
Frederick H.
1975
.
The Just War in the Middle Ages
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Schoske
Sylvia.
1982
. “Das Erschlagen der Feinde: Ikonographie und Stilistik der Feindvernichtung im alten Ägypten.” PhD thesis, Heidelberg Universität.

Schulman
Alan Richard.
1988
.
Ceremonial Execution and Public Rewards: Some Historical Scenes on New Kingdom Private Stelae
.
Freiburg
:
Universitätsverlag. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht
.

Seidel
Matthias
,
Schulz
Regine
.
2005
. Ägypten: Kunst und Architektur.
Mit Beiträgen von Abdel Ghaffar Shedid und Martina Ullmann
.
Köln
:
Könemann
.

Seton
David Robert.
1971
. “The King of Egypt Annihilating His Enemies: A Study of the Symbolism of Ancient Monarchy.” M.A. thesis, University of Birmingham.

Selden
John.
1640
.
De Iure Naturae Et Gentium Iuxta Disciplinam Ebraeorum
.
London
:
Excudebat Richardus Bishopius
.

Shaw
Ian.
1991
.
Egyptian Warfare and Weapons
.
Princes Risborough, UK
:
Shire
.

Silverman
David P.
1995
. “The Nature of Egyptian Kingship.” In
Ancient Egyptian Kingship
, edited by
O’Connor
David
,
Silverman
David P.
,
49
94
.
Leiden, New York, and Köln
:
Brill
.

Śliwa
Joachim.
1974
. “
Some Remarks Concerning Victorious Ruler Representations in Egyptian Art
.”
Forschungen und Berichte
16
:
97
117
.

Spalinger
Anthony John.
2005
.
War in Ancient Egypt: The New Kingdom
.
Malden, MA, and Oxford
:
Blackwell
.

Spalinger
Anthony John.
2013
. “New Kingdom Triumphs: A First Blush.” In
Rituals of Triumph in the Mediterranean World
, edited by
Spalinger
Anthony
,
Armstrong
Jeremy
,
95
122
.
Leiden and Boston
:
Brill
.

Spalinger
Anthony
,
Armstrong
Jeremy
, eds.
2013
.
Rituals of Triumph in the Mediterranean World
.
Leiden and Boston
:
Brill
.

Stromseth
Jane
,
Wippman
David
,
Brooks
Rosa
.
2006
.
Can Might Make Rights? Building the Rule of Law After Military Interventions
.
New York
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Syse
Henrik.
2006
. “
Plato, Thucydides, and the Education of Alcibiades
.”
Journal of Military Ethics
5
4
:
290
302
.

Syse
Henrik.
2010
. “
The Platonic Roots of Just War Doctrine: A Reading of Plato’s Republic
.”
Diametros
23
:
104
23
. Accessed October 23, 2015. http://www.Diametros.Iphils.Uj.Edu.Pl/Index.Php/Diametros/Article/View/384.

Trigger
Bruce G.
,
Kemp
Barry J.
,
O’Connor
David
,
Floyd
Alan B.
.
1983
.
Ancient Egypt: A Social History
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

United Nations (UN)
.
1948
. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. General Assembly, Paris, France, December 10, 1948. Accessed March 29, 2016. http://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human-rights/.

United Nations (UN)
.
1984
. Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment. Adopted and opened for signature, ratification, and accession by General Assembly resolution 39/46 of 10 December 1984 entry into force 26 June 1987, in accordance with article 27 (1). Accessed March 29, 2016. http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CAT.aspx.

Van Wees
Hans.
2010
. “Genocide in the Ancient World.” In
The Oxford Handbook of Genocide Studies
, edited by
Bloxham
Donald
,
Dirk Moses
A.
,
239
58
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Walzer
Michael.
2006
.
Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations
. 4th ed.
New York
:
Basic Books
.

Webster
David.
1999
. “Ancient Maya Warfare.” In
War and Society in the Ancient and Medieval Worlds: Asia, the Mediterranean, Europe, and Mesoamerica
, edited by
Raaflaub
Kurt
,
Rosenstein
Nathan
,
333
60
.
Cambridge, MA, and London
:
Harvard University Press
.

Westbrook
Raymond
, ed.
2003
.
A History of Ancient Near Eastern Law
.
Leiden and Boston
:
Brill
.

Wheeler
Everett L.
1987
. “
Ephorus and the Prohibition of Missiles
.”
Transactions of the American Philological Association
117
:
178
82
. Accessed October 15, 2015. http://www.jstor.org/stable/283965.

Wildung
Dieter.
1977
. “Erschlagen der Feinde.” In
Lexikon der Ägyptologie, Band II: Erntefest–Hordjedef
, edited by
Helk
Wolfgang
,
Westendorf
Wolfhart
,
114
17
.
Wiesbaden
:
Otto Harrassowitz
.

World Islamic Front Statement
.
1998
. Jihad Against Jews and Crusaders (23 February 1998). Accessed December 10, 2015. http://fas.org/irp/world/para/docs/980223-fatwa.htm.

Yoo
John C.
,
Ho
James C.
.
2003
. “
The Status of Terrorists
.”
Virginia Journal of International Law
44
:
207
28
. Accessed November 10, 2015. http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=2007&context=facpubs.

Zehr
Nahed Artoul.
2013
. “Legitimate Authority and the War against Al-Qaeda.” In
Just War: Authority, Tradition, and Practice
, edited by
Lang
Anthony F.
Jr.
,
O’Driscoll
Cian
,
Williams
John
,
97
113
.
Washington, DC
:
Georgetown University Press
.

Zimmerman
Martin.
2013
.
Gewalt: Die dunkle Seite der Antike
.
Munich
:
Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt
.

Ziskind
Jonathan Rosner.
1967
. “Aspects of International Law in the Ancient Near East.” PhD thesis, Columbia University.

Author notes

Author’s note: I would like to thank Anthony F. Lang Jr. and Cian O’Driscoll for their insightful and instructive comments on an early draft of this article. My thanks also go to the three anonymous reviewers and the editorial team at ISQ for their detailed feedback in preparing the article for publication. I was fortunate to spend June 2016 as a Visiting Fellow at the Stockholm Centre for the Ethics of War and Peace, where I gave a version of this article as a seminar paper. I express my warm gratitude to all the fellows and participants for their astute questions and suggestions.